Powers
of the Will, Benevolent Desires
And
the Spontaneous Motions of the Body
Francis
Hutcheson

A 2016 Editorial Note:
The writings of Francis Hutcheson (1694-1746) are more than unique in themselves.
They exemplify the fact that the origins of classic Western philosophy have essential
aspects in common with ancient Eastern traditions.
While influenced by Marcus Tullius Cicero
and other Western thinkers, Hutcheson examined significant issues relating also
to Raja Yoga. He was not necessarily aware of that, for the core of the best
ancient Greek and Roman philosophy is largely consistent with Eastern Raja Yoga
and related sciences.
Hutcheson’s definition of Moral Philosophy
is in harmony with the Wisdom of the Orient. He wrote:
“The intention of moral philosophy is to
direct men to that course of action which tends most effectually to promote
their greatest happiness and perfection; as far as it can be done by
observations and conclusions discoverable from the constitution of nature,
without any aids of supernatural revelation: these maxims, or rules of conduct
are therefore reputed as laws of nature, and the system or collection of them
is called the LAW of NATURE.” [1]
Readers can see that the 18 century
philosopher teaches in much of his writings a high form of ethical theosophy
and philosophy. According to W.
Leechman, F. Hutcheson demonstrates that the inner constitution of human beings,
which is formed by pursuing the general
good, “beautifully tallies with
the constitution of the universe”.[2]
And this is a central tenet of theosophy, ancient and modern.
The following text reproduces chapter one
in Hutcheson’s book “A System of Moral Philosophy” [3].
Besides its intrinsic value, the article can be read as a helpful commentary to the first 20
aphorisms in the book I of the Yoga Aphorisms of Patanjali.
Hutcheson invites us to
examine whether our everyday actions constitute isolated and mutually contradictory
events, or are consistent parts of a larger, benevolent, effective search for
happiness. If the second possibility is true, we are treading the right path.
The spelling is updated.
(Carlos Cardoso Aveline)
000
The Constitution of Human Nature
Francis Hutcheson
I. The intention of moral philosophy is to direct men to
that course of action which tends most effectually to promote their greatest
happiness and perfection; as far as it can be done by observations and
conclusions discoverable from the constitution of nature, without any aids of
supernatural revelation: these maxims, or rules of conduct are therefore
reputed as laws of nature, and the system or collection of them is called the
LAW of NATURE.
As human happiness, which is the end of this art,
cannot be distinctly known without the previous knowledge of the constitution
of this species, and of all its perceptive and active powers, and their natural
objects; (since happiness denotes the state of the soul arising from its
several grateful perceptions or modifications;) the most natural method in this
science must be first to inquire into the several powers and dispositions of
the species, whether perceptive or active, into its several natural
determinations, and the objects from whence its happiness can arise; and then
to compare together the several enjoyments this species is capable of
receiving, that we may discover what is its supreme happiness and perfection,
and what tenor of action is subservient to it.
In this inquiry we shall but briefly mention such
parts of our constitution, whether in body or mind, as are not of great
consequence in morals; avoiding unnecessary controversies, and often referring
to other authors for those points which have been tolerably well explained by
them. Thus we pass over many ingenious anatomical observations upon the
advantages and dignity of the human body above that of other animals. The
reader may find them in the anatomical authors, and Dr. Cumberland.
II. Consider mankind from their birth, you see a species
at first weaker and less capable of subsisting, without the aid of the adult,
than any other; and continuing longer in this infirm state. Animals of several
other kinds attain to their full vigour and the perfect use of all their powers
in a few months; and few require more than four or five years to their
maturity. Ten or twelve years are necessary to mankind before they can obtain
subsistence by their own art or labour, even in civilized societies, and in the
finest climates after they have been cleared of all beasts of prey. Many other
animals are both cloathed and armed by nature, and have all that is necessary
for their defence or convenient subsistence without any care or contrivance of
their own: the earth uncultivated offers them their food, and the woods or
rocks their shelter. Mankind are naked and unarmed; their more salutary and
agreeable food is more rare, requiring much art and labour: their bodies are
less fit to resist the injuries of weather, without more operose contrivances
for clothing and shelter. Their preservation therefore, in their tender years,
must depend on the care of the adult; and their lives must always continue
miserable if they are in solitude, without the aids of their fellows.
This is no unreasonable severity in the Author of
Nature [4] to our species. We shall
soon discover the natural remedy provided for this lasting imbecility of our
younger years, in the tender parental affection of a rational species; and the
final causes of it, in the several improvements we are capable of receiving.
The means of subsistence to our species require much contrivance and ingenuity:
we are capable of many noble enjoyments unknown to other animals, and depending
on useful and delightful arts, which we cannot attain to without a long
education, much instruction and imitation of others. How much time is requisite
for learning our mother-tongues? How much for dexterity even in the commonest
arts of agriculture, or in domestic service? Full strength of body, without a
mind equally advanced in knowledge and arts and social habits, would make us
ungovernable and untractable to our parents or instructors. Since we need to be
so long in subjection, we should not soon be able to shake off the necessary
and friendly yoke.
The External Senses
III. The natural principles
which first discover themselves are our external senses, with some small powers
of spontaneous motion, an appetite for food, and an instinct to receive and
swallow it. All these powers exert themselves in a way too dark for any of us ever
to apprehend completely [5]: much
less have the brutes any knowledge to direct them to the teats of their dams [6], or notion of the pressure of the
air upon which sucking depends. At first indeed we all alike act by instincts
wisely implanted by a superior hand. [7]
Our external senses soon introduce to the mind some
perceptions of pleasure and pain: and along with these perceptions there
immediately appears a natural constant determination to desire the one and
repel the other; to pursue whatever appears to be the cause or occasion of
pleasure, and to shun the causes of pain. These are probably our first notions
of natural good or evil, of happiness or misery.
The external senses are those “determinations of
nature by which certain perceptions constantly arise in the mind, when certain
impressions are made upon the organs of the body, or motions raised in them.”
Some of these perceptions are received solely by one sense, others may be
received by two or more. Of the former class, are these five sorts, viz.
colours, sounds, tastes, smells, cold or heat; some ingenious authors reckon
more: these we may call the proper ideas of sensation.
These sensations, as the learned agree, are not
pictures or representations of like external qualities in objects, nor of the
impression or change made in the bodily organs. They are either signals, as it were, of new events
happening to the body, of which experience and observation will show us the
cause; or marks, settled by the
Author of Nature, to show us what things are salutary, innocent, or hurtful; or
intimations of things not otherways discernable which may affect our state;
though these marks or signals bear no more resemblance to the external reality
than the report of a gun, or the flash of the powder, bears to the distress of
a ship. The pleasant sensations of taste, smell, and touch, generally arise
from objects innocent or salutary, when used in a moderate degree; the
disagreeable or painful sensations, from such as are pernicious or unfit for
common use. But sight and hearing seem not to be immediate avenues of pain;
scarcely is any visible form or any sound the immediate occasion of it; though
the violent motion of light or air may cause painful feelings; and yet by sight
and hearing the exquisite pleasures of beauty and harmony have access to the
soul, as well as the ideas of magnitudes, figures, situation, and motion. It is
by the former senses, and not by those, that we receive the pleasures commonly
called sensual.
The ideas of two or more senses are Duration, number,
extension, figure, motion, rest. Duration and number are applicable to every
perception or action of the mind, whether dependent upon bodily organs or not.
The simpler ideas of this class, which some call the Concomitant ideas of
sensation, are not generally either pleasant or painful. It is from some
complex modes of figure and motion that pleasure is perceived: beauty, from some proportions of figure with
colour: harmony, from some proportions of time as well as of tones or notes.
The proportions of numbers and figures are the field in which our reasoning
powers have the most free and vigorous exercise. Of these hereafter.
IV. There is another natural power of perception, always
exercised but not enough reflected upon, an inward sensation, perception, or
consciousness, of all the actions, passions, and modifications, of the mind; by
which its own perceptions, judgments, reasonings, affections, feelings, may
become its object: it knows them and fixes their names; and thus knows itself
in the same manner that it does bodies, by qualities immediately perceived,
though the substance of both be unknown.
These two powers of perception, sensation and consciousness,
introduce into the mind all its materials of knowledge. All our primary and
direct ideas or notions are derived from one or other of these sources. But the
mind never rests in bare perception; it compares the ideas received, discerns
their relations, marks the changes made in objects by our own action or that of
others; it inquires into the natures, proportions, causes, effects,
antecedents, consequents, of every thing, when it is not diverted by some
importunate appetite. These powers of judging and reasoning are more known and
better examined by all philosophers than any other, and therefore we pass them
over. All these several powers, of external sensation, consciousness, judging,
and reasoning, are commonly called the acts of the understanding.
V. Though there are many other sorts of finer
perceptions to be considered as natural to men, yet as some of them have the
acts of the will, the affections, and
passions, for their objects, it is necessary to take a short view of the will
and its natural determinations, before we proceed to these finer perceptions.
Here it is plain, as soon as any sense,
opinion, or reasoning, represents an object or event as immediately good or
pleasant, or as the means of future pleasure, or of security from evil, either
for ourselves or any person about whom we are solicitous, there arises
immediately a new motion of the soul, distinct from all sensation, perception,
or judgment, a desire of that object
or event. And upon perception or opinion of an object or event as the occasion
of pain or misery, or of the loss of good, arises a contrary motion called aversion; on all occasions of this sort,
these primary motions of the will naturally arise without any previous choice
or command, and are the general springs of action in every rational agent.
To the will
are commonly referred also two other modifications, or new states, arising from
our apprehensions of objects or events, as obtained or not obtained, according
to our previous desire; or repelled and prevented, or not, according to our
previous aversions; which are called joy and
sorrow. But as they do not
immediately move the soul to action, they seem rather new feelings or states of the
soul, than acts of the will, more resembling sensations than volitions. These
words however are often used promiscuously, as are many other names of the
actions and passions of the soul. Thus delight
or joy, is often used for the desire
of any event which when it befalls will give delight; so is sorrow, for fear and aversion. Thus we
have the [8] old division of the
motions of the will into four general species, Desire, Aversion, Joy and
Sorrow. Nor can we easily imagine any
spirit without these modifications and motions of Will of one sort or other.
The Deity [9] indeed, as he is
possessed of all power and all perfection, must be incapable of every
modification implying pain.
The acts of the will may be again divided
into two classes, according as one is pursuing good for himself, and repelling
the contrary, or pursuing good for others and repelling evils which threaten
them. The former we may call selfish,
the latter benevolent. Whatever subtile debates have been to prove that all motions of the will spring from one fountain, no man
can deny that we often have a real internal undissembled desire of the welfare
of others, and this in very different degrees.
Two Calm Determinations of the Will
VI. There
are two calm natural determinations of the will to be particularly considered
on this occasion. First, an invariable constant impulse toward one’s own
perfection and happiness of the highest kind. This [10] instinct operates in the bulk of mankind very confusedly; as
they do not reflect upon, or attend to, their own constitution and powers of
action and enjoyment; few have considered and compared the several enjoyments
they are capable of, or the several powers of action. But whosoever does so
will find a calm settled desire of the perfection of all our active powers, and
of the highest enjoyments, such as appear to us, upon comparison, of the
greatest importance to our happiness. Those who have not made such reflections
and comparisons, naturally desire all sorts of enjoyments they have any notion
of by their senses or any higher powers they have exercised, as far as they are
consistent with each other, or appear to be so; and desire the perfection of
such powers as they attend to. Where several enjoyments appear inconsistent,
the mind, while it is calm, naturally pursues, or desires in preference to
others, those which seem of the greatest importance to its happiness. So far
all agree.
The other determination alleged is toward the
universal happiness of others.[11] When
the soul is calm and attentive to the constitution and powers of other beings,
their natural actions and capacities of happiness and misery, and when the
selfish appetites and passions and desires are asleep, it is alleged that there
is a calm impulse of the soul to desire the greatest happiness and perfection
of the largest system within the compass of its knowledge. Our inward
consciousness abundantly testifies that there is such an impulse or
determination of the soul, and that it is truly ultimate, without reference to
any sort of happiness of our own. But here again, as few have considered the
whole system of beings knowable by men, we do not find this determination exerted
generally in all its extent; but we find natural desires of the happiness of
such individuals, or societies, or systems, as we have calmly considered, where
there has intervened no prejudice against them, or notion that their happiness
is any way opposite to our own.
As the notion of one’s own
highest happiness, or the greatest aggregate or sum of valuable enjoyments, is
not generally formed by men, it is not expressly desired or intended. And therefore we cannot say that every
particular calm desire of private good is aiming directly at that sum, and
pursuing its object under the notion of a necessary part of that sum. Men
naturally desire, even by calm motions of the soul, such objects as they
conceive useful or subservient to any valuable enjoyment, such as wealth,
power, honour, without this conception of their making a part of this greatest
sum. In like manner we have calm benevolent affections toward individuals, or
smaller societies of our fellows, where there has not preceded any consideration
of the most extensive system, and where they are not considered formally as
parts of this largest system, nor their happiness pursued as conducing to the
greatest sum of universal happiness. Such are our calm benevolent affections to
friends, countries, men of eminent worth, without any reference in our thoughts
to the most extensive system. We can make these references of all selfish
enjoyments pursued by us to the greatest sum of private happiness, whenever we
please; and we can in like manner refer all our calm particular kind affections
to the general extensive benevolence; and it is of great consequence to have
these large conceptions, and to make these references. But it is plain the several particular
affections, whether selfish or benevolent, operate, and that too [also] without turbulent or passionate
commotions, where no such references have preceded.
VII. But beside all these
calm motions of the will more or less extensive, there are many particular
passions and appetites which naturally arise on
their proper occasions, each terminating ultimately on its own
gratification, without further reference; and attended with violent, confused,
and uneasy sensations, which are apt to continue till the object or gratification is obtained.
Of these turbulent passions and appetites some are selfish, some benevolent,
and some may partake of both characters. Of the selfish are hunger, thirst,
lust, passions of sensual pleasure, wealth, power, or fame. Of the benevolent
kind are pity, condolence, congratulation, gratitude, conjugal and parental
affections, as often as they become violent and turbulent commotions of the
soul. Anger, envy, indignation, and some
others, may be of either kind, according as they arise either on account of
some opposition to our own interests, or to those of our friends or persons
loved and esteemed. These all arise on their natural occasions, where no
reference is made by the mind to its own greatest happiness, or to that of
others.
The difference
between the calm motions of the will and the passionate, whether of the selfish
or benevolent kinds, must be obvious to any who consider how often we find them
acting in direct opposition.[12]
Thus anger or lust will draw us one way; and a calm regard, either to our highest
interest the greatest sum of private good, or to some particular interest, will
draw the opposite way: sometimes the passion conquering the calm principle, and
sometimes being conquered by it. The calm desire of wealth will force one,
though with reluctance, into splendid expenses, when necessary to gain a good
bargain or a gainful employment; while the passion of avarice is repining at
these expenses. The sedate desire of a child’s or a friend’s virtue and honour
and improvement, will make us send them abroad amidst dangers; while the
parental and friendly passions are opposing this purpose. Gratitude, pity, and
friendly passions, solicite to one side; and love of a country, or a yet more
extensive benevolence, may be soliciting on the other side. We correct and
restrain our children, we engage them in uneasy studies and labours, out of
calm good-will, while this tender passion is opposing everything that is uneasy
to them. Desire of life persuades to abstinence, to painful cures and nauseous
potions, in opposition to the appetites destined to preserve life in the order
of nature.
As there belong
to the understanding not only the lower powers of sensation, common to us with
the brutes, but also those of reasoning, consciousness, and pure intellect, as it is called; so to
the will belong not only the bodily appetites and turbulent passions, but the
several calm and extensive affections of a nobler order.
Spontaneous Motions of the Body
VIII. To the Will we also ascribe the power of Spontaneous Motion; since, in
consequence of our willing it, we find many parts of the body move as we
incline. All its parts are not thus subjected to be moved as we please; but
only such as it is necessary or useful in life for us to have thus subjected. The
inward parts go on, in those motions upon which the continuance of life
immediately depends, without any acts of our will; nor can we directly, by any
volition, accelerate or retard them. To superintend motions continually
necessary would engross the mind perpetually, and make it incapable of any
other business. Nor does every motion or impression on the parts of the body
excite sensations in the soul. There is no sensation of the internal motions on
which life immediately depends, while the body is in good order. Such sensation
would be an uneasy useless distraction of the mind from all valuable purposes;
as we experience, when a disease makes the contraction of the heart, or
beatings of the pulse, become sensible. Sensations indicate only such changes,
and new events, or objects, as it is convenient we should be apprised of. Thus
volitions move the head, the eyes, the mouth, the tongue, the limbs, and, that
exquisite instrument of a rational inventive and artful species, the hand. All
these are plain indications of the wise and benign counsel of our Creator.[13] Nay our limbs are moved
immediately in consequence of the contraction of muscles, and of some power
sent down by nerves from the head. But in our spontaneous motions we neither
know nor will these intermediate steps: we intend the last motion; and those
other motions are performed without any knowledge or will of ours. Sensation in
like manner immediately ensues upon some motion in a nerve continued to the
brain: we perceive no motion in the brain; but have a sensation immediately referred
to the extremity of the body where the impression was made, and seeming to
occupy that place; in a matter quite inexplicable. These considerations have
led some ingenious and pious men to conclude that a superior Being, or the
Deity himself, is the sole physical cause of all our motions [14]; according to certain general
laws; and the sole efficient cause of all sensations too, in the like manner.
NOTES:
[1] “A
System of Moral Philosophy”, by Francis Hutcheson, Cambridge University Press,
2014, a facsimile copy of the 1755 edition, volume I, p. 1 (CCA)
[2] “A
System of Moral Philosophy”, Francis Hutcheson, Cambridge University Press,
2014, preface by W. Leechman, p. xix. (CCA)
[3] “A
System of Moral Philosophy”, Francis Hutcheson, 1755, pp. 1-14. (CCA)
[4] “The Author of Nature” - the
symbolical and poetical personalization of universal Law and the collective
cosmic intelligences which work under it must be handled with care in
theosophy, and should not be taken in any literal sense. (CCA)
[5] “All these powers exert themselves in a way too dark
for any of us ever to apprehend completely”. Indeed, although there is nothing
“unconscious” in Nature or in the Universe, one can see that there are subconscious
or involuntary events and levels in human life. These were called “dark
perceptions” before late 19th and early 20th century Psychologists and
Psychoanalysts. Examine for instance the book “Mémoire Sur Les Perceptions Obscures”, by Maine de Biran
(1766-1824). The work is available at our associated websites and can be seen
by clicking here. (CCA)
[6] Dam - classical English alteration of “dame”, meaning
the female parent of an animal, especially a domestic mammal. (CCA)
[7] Superior hand, id
est, the Law of Karma. (CCA)
[8] Note by Hutcheson: See Cicero’s Tuscul., lib. III and IV. The
Stoics, the avowed enemies of the passions, allowed [such motions of the soul] in the perfected character, even the Deity;
but all these of a higher sort than the turbulent passions; of which
distinction hereafter.
[9]
Deity: One’s higher self or spiritual
soul, and/or the universal Law. (CCA)
[10] Note by Hutcheson: We
need no apology, for using the word ‘instinct’ for our highest powers, to those
who know the Latin language. Appetite is in our language much confined to lower
powers; but in Latin the word is applied to the highest.
[11] “Universal happiness of others”. Pure theosophy starts here, for an
altruistic purpose comes from the higher self. The first object of the modern
theosophical movement aims at universal
brotherhood, which leads to universal
happiness. (CCA)
[12] Note by
Hutcheson: See this well described in “Plato. Rep. I. 9.”
and “Aristot. Eth. Nicom.”.
[13]
“Creator” - the symbolic personalization in Christian parlance of one’s own
higher self, Atma-Buddhi, and of the Law of Karma. At each new incarnation the
Law “creates” us, and “creates” the world we live in. (CCA)
[14] The
Sun is such Cause, on the physical level, as the spiritual levels of the Sun
are the source of our spiritual evolution, according to ancient religions and
to philosophy, with which the modern theosophy agrees. (CCA)
000
The above text is available in the associated websites since August 2016. It reproduces Chapter I of Book I, pp. 1-14 in the first volume of the work “A System of Moral Philosophy”, by Francis Hutcheson, which was published in London in the year 1755. The spelling has been updated.
000
On 14 September 2016, a group of students
decided to found the Independent Lodge
of Theosophists. Two of the priorities adopted by the ILT are learning from the past and building a better
future.
000